The American Psychiatric Association (APA) has updated its Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, including with new information specifically addressed to individuals in the European Economic Area. As described in the Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, this website utilizes cookies, including for the purpose of offering an optimal online experience and services tailored to your preferences.

Please read the entire Privacy Policy and Terms of Use. By closing this message, browsing this website, continuing the navigation, or otherwise continuing to use the APA's websites, you confirm that you understand and accept the terms of the Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, including the utilization of cookies.

×
EditorialsFull Access

Bayesian Dysconnections

It is a pleasure to comment on the Greenman et al. (1) study of parieto-prefrontal disconnection in schizophrenia. The authors’ work brings together advanced data analytics and theoretical neurobiology to paint a compelling, mechanistic picture of the disintegration of the psyche in schizophrenia. In fact, some of the analyses and constructs are so cutting edge, even the most academic of us might be forgiven for feeling out of our depth. I will therefore use a conversational style to unpack the simplicity and importance of this work and how it cuts across emerging themes in schizophrenia research.

In brief, the authors furnish clear evidence for aberrant belief updating in the kind of higher cognitive processing that people with schizophrenia find particularly difficult. Crucially, the mechanisms that underwrite this difficulty are tied down to specific—and directed—connections from posterior (parietal) parts of the brain, involved in processing numbers, to anterior (prefrontal) parts of the brain responsible for deep (hierarchical) processing and implicit working memory. The authors then validate this selective and pernicious disconnection in terms of its predictive validity, using polygenetic risk for schizophrenia (in control subjects) and a propensity for delusional thinking (in people with schizophrenia). This remarkable finding did not come out of the blue: it inherits from decades—if not centuries—of careful thinking about the psychopathology and pathophysiology of schizophrenia. In what follows, I will briefly rehearse the back story that underwrites this study and then focus on its particular contributions that rest on an eclectic approach to the deficit at hand.

The Back Story: Disconnection and the Bayesian Brain

Greenman et al. (1) have discovered, at its simplest, a particular disconnection between parietal and prefrontal regions that is evinced in a context-sensitive way. In other words, they characterize a failure of functional integration during working memory manipulation, relative to simply maintaining items (i.e., numbers) in mind. In itself, this is important because it is a statement about connectivity, or, more precisely, a functional dysconnection. This notion was articulated formally about three decades ago, notably by the coauthors of the present study (2, 3). The notion of schizophrenia as a disconnection syndrome comes, historically, in two flavors. It can be traced back to the sejunction hypothesis of Wernicke that entails a disruption of the (white matter) “organs of connection” (4). The alternative sort of dysconnection can plausibly be attributed to Bleuler (5), who conceived of a more nuanced, context-sensitive functional disintegration that we would currently see in terms of a synaptopathy or, more precisely, a loss of ability to contextualize or modulate synaptic efficacy (6). On this view, macroscopic changes seen in brain imaging and neuropathological studies stem from a primary synaptopathy that, almost inevitably, implicates neuromodulatory systems such as the ascending neuromodulatory transmitters (e.g., dopamine, and its interaction with NMDA receptors, particularly on fast-spiking inhibitory GABAergic interneurons).

Perhaps it is of no surprise that people started taking the dysconnection view more seriously with the advent of whole brain functional imaging, where, for the first time, it became possible to measure effective connectivity in vivo. Interestingly, the dynamic causal modeling procedures used in the Greenman et al. study were originally developed—like statistical parametric mapping—for schizophrenia research. Over the subsequent decades, brain imaging shifted its focus from neophrenology and functional segregation toward the directed (effective) connectivity that underwrites functional integration and the disintegration of the psyche proposed by Bleuler. This is all well and good, but it says nothing about psychopathology and even less about delusions. So where does the story go from here?

Precision Psychiatry

With the new millennium, the cognitive sciences started to embrace predictive processing as a way of understanding functional brain architectures—and neuronal message passing within that distributed (and usually hierarchical) anatomy (79). Predictive processing usually appeals to the notion of the Bayesian brain to emphasize the assimilation of sensory evidence under uncertainty—or its complement, precision (9). In brief, this account treats the brain like a little scientist, making inferences about the causes of (sensory) data. These inferences follow naturally from Bayes’s rule, which says that the probability of a cause, given some data, is proportional to the probability of the data, given the cause, multiplied by the (prior) probability of the cause. This offers a crisp and formal way to describe belief updating, where a prior belief is combined with sensory evidence to produce a posterior or Bayesian belief.

Before the advent of predictive processing—e.g., hierarchal predictive coding models of message passing in the brain (10)—functionalist versions of disintegration used notions like aberrant salience, with a nod to the role of dopamine in the reward learning literature (11). Over the past decade, a more precise formalism became available, in which salience could be understood in terms of the reliability or newsworthiness of certain messages or efferents passed along neuronal connections (12). Perhaps the easiest way to understand this is in terms of predictive coding (a.k.a. Bayesian filtering). Put simply, this regards neuronal message passing as exchanges of signals in the service of updating Bayesian beliefs about the causes of sensory input. This usually involves the forward passing of prediction errors to update Bayesian beliefs at higher levels in a cortical hierarchy. These updated beliefs or expectations then generate predictions that descend to lower hierarchical levels, in order to evaluate a prediction error. The key move in this scheme is to note that not all prediction errors are equal. In other words, there are certain situations in which prediction errors convey precise information and others in which they are unreliable (e.g., visually palpating a dark room). This means that the brain has to estimate the precision of prediction errors. This estimation can be regarded as the basis of sensory attention and attenuation (13).

This is interesting. From the purely theoretical perspective of predictive processing, one might imagine that aberrant belief updating and formation—in the setting of a Bayesian brain—will be particularly sensitive to the neuromodulatory mechanisms that set the attentional gain or precision of ascending prediction errors conveyed by forward connections (14). However, this is exactly the endpoint of the functional dysconnection story: namely, an aberrant modulation of synaptic efficacy. This convergent evolution of theoretical and empirical arguments also fits comfortably with treatments of schizophrenia in terms of excitation-inhibition balance in the cortex and the attending synaptic mechanisms (1519).

A Slight Problem

In the past decade, a whole host of psychiatric and neurological conditions have been explained in terms of a failure to modulate the precision of prediction errors (i.e., neuronal messages). Perhaps the best example here is autism, which is generally ascribed to a failure to attenuate the precision of sensory prediction errors: i.e., a failure of sensory attenuation (14). Without going into detail, this presents an interesting challenge for the notion of delusions (16). If sensory information is afforded too much precision in schizophrenia, then one would imagine that delusional beliefs—that play the role of prior beliefs—would be more susceptible to revision, as they are updated by unattenuated prediction errors. However, much of the phenomenology of delusion formation—and things like jumping to conclusions (20)—suggests an overreliance on higher-level prior beliefs. This suggests that delusional beliefs are more resistant to ascending prediction errors, rendering them recalcitrant and immutable. This is currently a focus of many debates and papers. Perhaps one could regard delusion formation as a paradoxical lesion (21). In other words, a failure of sensory attenuation calls for a complementary rebalancing of hierarchical message passing by increasing the precision of prior beliefs. This compensatory pathophysiology means that high-level beliefs would become desensitized to unattenuated prediction errors from below. If this is the right explanation for delusions, what would one expect to see empirically?

Disconnections of a Certain Kind

We would expect to see a context-sensitive reduction in the influence of a lower (e.g., parietal) part of the brain on a higher (e.g., prefrontal) part—in short, a selective and context-sensitive reduction in the effective connectivity of forward connections. This is exactly what Greenman et al. report in this issue. Furthermore, not only were the authors able to demonstrate this context-sensitive (manipulation-dependent) failure to respond to ascending prediction errors, they were also able to show that alternative explanations for this dysconnectivity can be discounted. To do this, they used their experimental design to look for variations in (dynamic causal modeling estimates of) effective connectivity to show that in non-schizophrenia control subjects, they predict polygenetic risk scores for schizophrenia. Crucially, this predictive validity cannot be explained away by confounding factors in people with schizophrenia.

In a complementary analysis, the authors addressed between-subject variability within the schizophrenia group using a rather clever analysis. Instead of just testing for group-by-(cognitive) condition interactions, they used predictions of the condition-specific connectivity during the manipulation condition, based on the connectivity established during the maintenance. Crucially, they used the control subjects to map from the pattern of connectivity during maintenance to the pattern instantiated during manipulation. This enabled them to establish a neurotypical, condition-specific functional connectome for people with schizophrenia. Finally, deviations from this pattern were then shown to predict the propensity for delusional beliefs in this group. This disclosed a remarkable correlation, such that as delusion severity increases, people with schizophrenia failed to sensitize themselves to parietal (feedforward) afferents in the way that somebody without schizophrenia would.

In summary, Greenman et al. leverage a series of high-end analytics to ask a simple question that emerges from the theoretical neurobiology of schizophrenia, namely, can we explain delusions in terms of a failure of (Bayesian) belief updating, in which higher-level beliefs become resistant to revision by ascending hierarchical connections in the brain? I think that they can congratulate themselves on providing us with an affirmative answer.

Wellcome Centre for Human Neuroimaging and Queen Square Institute of Neurology, University College London; and National Hospital for Neurology and Neurosurgery, London.
Send correspondence to Dr. Friston ().

The author reports no financial relationships with commercial interests.

References

1 Greenman DLB, La MAN, Shah S, et al.: Parietal-prefrontal feedforward connectivity in association with schizophrenia genetic risk and delusions. Am J Psychiatry 2020; 177:1151–1158AbstractGoogle Scholar

2 Weinberger DR: A connectionist approach to the prefrontal cortex. J Neuropsychiatry Clin Neurosci 1993; 5:241–253Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

3 Friston KJ, Frith CD: Schizophrenia: a disconnection syndrome? Clin Neurosci 1995; 3:89–97MedlineGoogle Scholar

4 Ungvari GS: The Wernicke-Kleist-Leonhard school of psychiatry. Biol Psychiatry 1993; 34:749–752Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

5 Bob P, Mashour GA: Schizophrenia, dissociation, and consciousness. Conscious Cogn 2011; 20:1042–1049Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

6 Friston K, Brown HR, Siemerkus J, et al.: The dysconnection hypothesis (2016). Schizophr Res 2016; 176:83–94Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

7 Clark A: Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behav Brain Sci 2013; 36:181–204Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

8 Hohwy J: The Predictive Mind. Oxford, UK, Oxford University Press, 2013CrossrefGoogle Scholar

9 Knill DC, Pouget A: The Bayesian brain: the role of uncertainty in neural coding and computation. Trends Neurosci 2004; 27:712–719Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

10 Rao RP, Ballard DH: Predictive coding in the visual cortex: a functional interpretation of some extra-classical receptive-field effects. Nat Neurosci 1999; 2:79–87Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

11 Kapur S: Psychosis as a state of aberrant salience: a framework linking biology, phenomenology, and pharmacology in schizophrenia. Am J Psychiatry 2003; 160:13–23LinkGoogle Scholar

12 Clark A: The many faces of precision (replies to commentaries on “Whatever next? Neural prediction, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science”). Front Psychol 2013; 4:270Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

13 Adams RA, Stephan KE, Brown HR, et al.: The computational anatomy of psychosis. Front Psychiatry 2013; 4:47Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

14 Palmer CJ, Seth AK, Hohwy J: The felt presence of other minds: predictive processing, counterfactual predictions, and mentalising in autism. Conscious Cogn 2015; 36:376–389Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

15 Lisman J: Excitation, inhibition, local oscillations, or large-scale loops: what causes the symptoms of schizophrenia? Curr Opin Neurobiol 2012; 22:537–544Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

16 Sterzer P, Adams RA, Fletcher P, et al.: The predictive coding account of psychosis. Biol Psychiatry 2018; 84:634–643Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

17 Wang XJ, Krystal JH: Computational psychiatry. Neuron 2014; 84:638–654Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

18 Barch DM, Carter CS, Dakin SC, et al.: The clinical translation of a measure of gain control: the contrast-contrast effect task. Schizophr Bull 2012; 38:135–143Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

19 Butler PD, Silverstein SM, Dakin SC: Visual perception and its impairment in schizophrenia. Biol Psychiatry 2008; 64:40–47Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

20 Moutoussis M, Bentall RP, El-Deredy W, et al.: Bayesian modelling of jumping-to-conclusions bias in delusional patients. Cogn Neuropsychiatry 2011; 16:422–447Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

21 Young MP, Hilgetag C, Scannell JW: Models of paradoxical lesion effects and rules of inference for imputing function to structure in the brain. Neurocomputing 1999; 26-27:933–938CrossrefGoogle Scholar